Metabolism involves performing the same transformation uniformly to instances of the same type of object: cooking all the eggs, or cleaning/dirtying all the forks. Often times, however, an agent will work toward different kinds of goals at once. This can often be done by interleaving the actions from solutions to the individual goals. We will say that an interleaving I is a function that returns one or the other of its first two arguments, depending on a third state argument:
When the last two arguments of I are policies, the result is itself a policy, so we will define the notation:
If we wanted to simultaneously make toast and cook an egg, then a good interleaving of a toast-making policy and an egg-cooking policy would be one that chose the egg-making policy whenever the egg had finished its current cooking step (and so was ready to be flipped or removed from the pan) and chose the toast-making policy when the egg was busy cooking. A bad interleaving would be one that always chose the toast-making policy.
An interleaving I is fair for and
if starting
from any state,
will after some finite number of steps
have executed both
and
at least once. Finally, we will
say that two bindings are independent if they map disjoint sets
of components to their images. Binding independence is a special case
of subgoal independence: two policies can't possibly interfere if they
alter distinct state components. Fairness and binding independence
are sufficient conditions for an interleaving to solve a conjunctive
goal:
Proof: Since I is a fair interleaving, each of the two policies will be executed in finite time, regardless of starting state. By induction, for any n, there is a number of steps after which I is guaranteed to have executed at least n steps of each policy.
The policy is the composition of a policy
for a state
space
with a binding. If
solves
and halts, then it
must do so by having
solve
and halt in some finite
number of steps n. During execution, the environment goes through a
series of states
which project under to a series of states
we claim that any execution of the interleaving must
bring the environment through a sequence of states that project under
to
that is, a string of states in which appears at least once,
then
, appears at least once, and so on. The only state
transitions that appear are from some
to itself or to
. Suppose it were otherwise. Then there must be a point at
which this series is broken:
where s is neither nor
. We have two cases.
Case 1:
executed the transition. Then we have that
, a contradiction. Case 2:
executed the
transition. Then
has changed one of the state components
mapped by
and so
and
are not independent, a
contradiction. Thus the interleaving solves
. By the same
reasoning, it must halt in
, since
halts in
. Also
by the same reasoning, it must solve
and halt, and hence, must
solve the intersection and halt.
A useful corollary to this is that when the same policy is applied under two independent bindings, the bindings can be safely interleaved, that is, interleaving commutes with binding: